ethics和moral moralityy的区别?

ethnic 和morality区别_百度作业帮
ethnic 和morality区别
ethnic 和morality区别
是否写错了?应该是ethic(没有字母'n') 和morality的区别吧?ethnic是『xin 仰』相关的,而morality - 道德.关于ethic和morality的区别,也就是ethic和moral的区别(morality是moral的标准和体系化).ethic和moral都涉及‘对’和‘错’的判定标准.二者非常接近,但区分也是明显的.ethic是『伦理』,而moral是『道德』,最大的分别在于:moral是个人自身的‘对’和‘错’的标准,相对抽象,主观而且常和个人的宗·教·或·信·仰有关;而ethic是外部的群体意识形成的一种道德标准,相较moral更具体,是在个人moral的基础上,被群体认可,又施叫或影响个人moral的体系.ethic是关于moral的科学,而moral是对ethic的实践.群体意识的ethic源于个体的moral,又反作用于个人的moral,二者相互依存.From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
For other uses, see .
in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.
Ethics or moral philosophy is the branch of
that involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong . The term ethics derives from the
word ?θικ?? ethikos, which is derived from the word ?θο?
(, “custom”). The branch of philosophy
comprises the sub-branches of Ethics and , each concerned with concepts of value.
As a branch of philosophy, ethics investigates the questions “What is the best way for people to live?” and “What
are right or wrong in particular circumstances?” In practice, ethics seeks to resolve questions of human morality, by defining concepts such as , right and ,
and . As a field of intellectual enquiry, moral philosophy also is related to the fields of , , and .
The three major areas of study within ethics are:
, concerning the theoretical meaning and reference of moral propositions, and how their
(if any) can be determined
, concerning the practical means of determining a moral course of action
, concerning what a person is obligated (or permitted) to do in a specific situation or a particular domain of action
of this section is . Relevant discussion may be found on the . Please do not remove this message until the . (June 2014)
Dino Lobaton states that "standard definitions of ethics have typically included such phrases as 'the science of the ideal human character' or 'the science of moral duty' ". Richard William Paul and
define ethics as "a set of concepts and principles that guide us in determining what behavior helps or harms sentient creatures". The
states that the word ethics is "commonly used interchangeably with '' ... and sometimes it is used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition, group or individual."[] Paul and Elder state that most people confuse ethics with behaving in accordance with social conventions, religious beliefs and the law and don't treat ethics as a stand-alone concept.
The word "ethics" in English refers to several things. It can refer to philosophical ethics—a project that attempts to use reason in order to answer various kinds of ethical questions.[] It can also be used to describe a particular person's own, idiosyncratic principles or habits. For example: "Joe has good ethics." It may also be used to characterize the questions of right-conduct in some specific sphere, even when such right-conduct is not examined philosophically: "business ethics," or "the ethics of child-rearing" may refer, but need not refer, to a philosophical examination of such issues.[] Philosophical ethics, or "ethical theory," is not the exclusive use of the term "ethics" in English.[]
Main article:
Meta-ethics asks how we understand, know about, and what we mean when we talk about what is right and what is wrong. An ethical question fixed on some particular practical question—such as, "Should I eat this particular piece of chocolate cake?"—cannot be a meta-ethical question. A meta-ethical question is abstract and relates to a wide range of more specific practical questions. For example, "Is it ever possible to have secure knowledge of what is right and wrong?" would be a meta-ethical question.
Meta-ethics has always accompanied philosophical ethics. For example, Aristotle implies that less precise knowledge is possible in ethics than in other spheres of inquiry, and he regards ethical knowledge as depending upon habit and acculturation in a way that makes it distinctive from other kinds of knowledge. Meta-ethics is also important in 's
from 1903. In it he first wrote about what he called the . Moore was seen to reject
in ethics, in his . This made thinkers look again at second order questions about ethics. Earlier, the Scottish
had put forward a similar view on the difference between .
Studies of how we know in ethi this is similar to the contrast between descriptivists and non-descriptivists. Non-cognitivism is the claim that when we judge something as right or wrong, this is neither true nor false. We may for example be only expressing our emotional feelings about these things. Cognitivism can then be seen as the claim that when we talk about right and wrong, we are talking about matters of fact.
of ethics is about value-bearing things or properties, i.e. the kind of things or stuff referred to by ethical propositions. Non-descriptivists and non-cognitivists believe that ethics does not need a specific ontology, since ethical propositions do not refer. This is known as an anti-realist position. Realists on the other hand must explain what kind of entities, properties or states are relevant for ethics, how they have value, and why they guide and motivate our actions.
Main article:
Normative ethics is the study of ethical action. It is the branch of ethics that investigates the set of questions that arise when considering how one ought to act, morally speaking. Normative ethics is distinct from
because it examines standards for the rightness and wrongness of actions, while meta-ethics studies the meaning of moral language and the metaphysics of moral facts. Normative ethics is also distinct from , as the latter is an empirical investigation of people's moral beliefs. To put it another way, descriptive ethics would be concerned with determining what proportion of people believe that killing is always wrong, while normative ethics is concerned with whether it is correct to hold such a belief. Hence, normative ethics is sometimes called prescriptive, rather than descriptive. However, on certain versions of the meta-ethical view called , moral facts are both descriptive and prescriptive at the same time.
Traditionally, normative ethics (also known as moral theory) was the study of what makes actions right and wrong. These theories offered an overarching moral principle one could appeal to in resolving difficult moral decisions.
At the turn of the 20th century, moral theories became more complex and are no longer concerned solely with rightness and wrongness, but are interested in many different kinds of moral status. During the middle of the century, the study of normative ethics declined as meta-ethics grew in prominence. This focus on meta-ethics was in part caused by an intense linguistic focus in
and by the popularity of .
published , noteworthy in its pursuit of moral arguments and eschewing of meta-ethics. This publication set the trend for renewed interest in normative ethics.
Main article:
Virtue ethics describes the character of a moral agent as a driving force for ethical behavior, and is used to describe the ethics of , , and other early Greek philosophers.
(469–399 BC) was one of the first
to encourage both scholars and the common citizen to turn their attention from the outside world to the condition of humankind. In this view,
bearing on human life was placed highest, while all other knowledge were secondary.
was considered necessary for success and inherently an essential good. A self-aware person will act completely within his capabilities to his pinnacle, while an ignorant person will flounder and encounter difficulty. To Socrates, a person must become aware of every fact (and its context) relevant to his existence, if he wishes to attain self-knowledge. He posited that people will naturally do what is good, if they know what is right. Evil or bad actions are the result of ignorance. If a criminal was truly aware of the intellectual and spiritual consequences of his actions, he would neither commit nor even consider committing those actions. Any person who knows what is truly right will automatically do it, according to Socrates. While he correlated knowledge with , he similarly equated virtue with . The truly wise man will know what is right, do what is good, and therefore be happy.:32–33
(384–323 BC) posited an ethical system that may be termed "self-realizationism." In Aristotle's view, when a person acts in accordance with his nature and realizes his full potential, he will do good and be content. At birth, a baby is not a person, but a potential person. To become a "real" person, the child's inherent potential must be realized. Unhappiness and frustration are caused by the unrealized potential of a person, leading to failed goals and a poor life. Aristotle said, " does nothing in vain." Therefore, it is imperative for people to act in accordance with their nature and develop their latent talents in order to be content and complete. Happiness was held to be the ultimate goal. All other things, such as civic life or , are merely means to the end. Self-realization, the awareness of one's nature and the development of one's talents, is the surest path to happiness.:33–35
Aristotle asserted that man had three natures: vegetable (physical/metabolism), animal (emotional/appetite) and rational (mental/conceptual). Physical nature can be assuaged through exercise and care, emotional nature through indulgence of instinct and urges, and mental through human reason and developed potential. Rational development was considered the most important, as essential to philosophical self-awareness and as uniquely human.
was encouraged, with the extremes seen as degraded and immoral. For example,
is the moderate virtue between the extremes of
and . Man should not simply live, but live well with conduct governed by moderate virtue. This is regarded as difficult, as virtue denotes doing the right thing, to the right person, at the right time, to the proper extent, in the correct fashion, for the right reason.:35–37
philosopher
posited that the greatest good was contentment and serenity. Peace of mind, or , was
self-mastery over one's desires and emotions leads to spiritual peace. The "unconquerable will" is central to this philosophy. The individual's will should be independent and inviolate. Allowing a person to disturb the mental equilibrium is in essence offering yourself in slavery. If a person is free to anger you at will, you have no control over your internal world, and therefore no freedom. Freedom from material attachments is also necessary. If a thing breaks, the person should not be upset, but realize it was a thing that could break. Similarly, if someone should die, those close to them should hold to their serenity because the loved one was made of flesh and blood destined to death. Stoic philosophy says to accept things that cannot be changed, resigning oneself to existence and enduring in a rational fashion. Death is not feared. People do not "lose" their life, but instead "return", for they are returning to God (who initially gave what the person is as a person). Epictetus said difficult problems in life should not be avoided, but rather embraced. They are spiritual exercises needed for the health of the spirit, just as physical exercise is required for the health of the body. He also stated that sex and sexual desire are to be avoided as the greatest threat to the integrity and equilibrium of a man's mind. Abstinence is highly desirable. Epictetus said remaining abstinent in the face of temptation was a victory for which a man could be proud.:38–41
Main article:
Modern virtue ethics was popularized during the late 20th century in large part as a response to 's "". Anscombe argues that consequentialist and deontological ethics are only feasible as universal theories if the two schools ground themselves in divine law. As a deeply devoted Christian herself, Anscombe proposed that either those who do not give ethical credence to notions of divine law take up virtue ethics, which does not necessitate universal laws as agents themselves are investigated for virtue or vice and held up to "universal standards," or that those who wish to be utilitarian or consequentialist ground their theories in religious conviction. , who wrote the book , was a key contributor and proponent of modern virtue ethics, although MacIntyre supports a relativistic account of virtue based on , not objective standards. , a contemporary virtue ethicist, objects to MacIntyre's relativism, among that of others, and responds to relativist objections to form an objective account in her work "Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach." Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century
blended the Eastern virtue ethics and the Western virtue ethics, with some modifications to suit the 21st Century, and formed a part of contemporary virtue ethics.
Main article:
Hedonism posits that the principal ethic is maximizing
and minimizing . There are several schools of Hedonist thought ranging from those advocating the indulgence of even momentary desires to those teaching a pursuit of spiritual bliss. In their consideration of consequences, they range from those advocating
regardless of the pain and expense to others, to those stating that the most ethical pursuit maximizes pleasure and happiness for the most people.:37
Founded by
of Cyrene,
supported immediate gratification or pleasure. "Eat, drink and be merry, for tomorrow we die." Even fleeting desires should be indulged, for fear the opportunity should be forever lost. There was little to no concern with the future, the present dominating in the pursuit for immediate pleasure. Cyrenaic hedonism encouraged the pursuit of enjoyment and indulgence without hesitation, believing pleasure to be the only good.:37
Main article:
Epicurean ethics is a hedonist form of virtue ethics.
"presented a sustained argument that pleasure, correctly understood, will coincide with virtue". He rejected the extremism of the , believing some pleasures and indulgences to be detrimental to human beings.
observed that indiscriminate indulgence sometimes resulted in negative consequences. Some experiences were therefore rejected out of hand, and some unpleasant experiences endured in the present to ensure a better life in the future. To Epicurus the summum bonum, or greatest good, was prudence, exercised through moderation and caution. Excessive indulgence can be destructive to pleasure and can even lead to pain. For example, eating one food too often will cause a person to lose taste for it. Eating too much food at once will lead to discomfort and ill-health. Pain and fear were to be avoided. Living was essentially good, barring pain and illness. Death was not to be feared. Fear was considered the source of most unhappiness. Conquering the fear of death would naturally lead to a happier life. Epicurus reasoned if there was an afterlife and immortality, the fear of death was irrational. If there was no life after death, then the person would not be alive to suffer, he would be non-existent in death. It is irrational to fret over circumstances that do not exist, such as one's state in death in the absence of an afterlife.:37–38
Main article:
, also known as Mohist consequentialism, is an ethical theory that evaluates the moral worth of an action based on how much it contributes to the basic goods of a state. The
describes Mohist consequentialism, dating back to the 5th century BC, as "a remarkably sophisticated version based on a plurality of intrinsic goods taken as constitutive of human welfare." Unlike utilitarianism, which views pleasure as a moral good, "the basic goods in Mohist consequentialist thinking are ... order, material wealth, and increase in population". During 's era, war and famines were common, and population growth was seen as a moral necessity for a harmonious society. The "material wealth" of Mohist consequentialism refers to
like shelter and clothing, and the "order" of Mohist consequentialism refers to Mozi's stance against warfare and violence, which he viewed as pointless and a threat to social stability.
, in , writes that the moral goods of Mohism "are interrelated: more basic wealth, th more people, then more production and wealth ... if people have plenty, they would be good, filial, kind, and so on unproblematically." The Mohists believed that morality is based on "promoting the benefit of all under heaven and eliminating harm to all under heaven." In contrast to Bentham's views, state consequentialism is not utilitarian because it is not hedonistic or individualistic. The importance of outcomes that are good for the community outweigh the importance of individual pleasure and pain.
Main article:
Consequentialism refers to moral theories that hold that the consequences of a particular action form the basis for any valid moral judgment about that action (or create a structure for judgment, see ). Thus, from a consequentialist standpoint, a morally right action is one that produces a good outcome, or consequence. This view is often expressed as the
"The ends justify the means".
The term "consequentialism" was coined by
in her essay "" in 1958, to describe what she saw as the central error of certain moral theories, such as those propounded by
and . Since then, the term has become common in English-language ethical theory.
The defining feature of consequentialist moral theories is the weight given to the consequences in evaluating the rightness and wrongness of actions. In consequentialist theories, the consequences of an action or rule generally outweigh other considerations. Apart from this basic outline, there is little else that can be unequivocally said about consequentialism as such. However, there are some questions that many consequentialist theories address:
What sort of consequences count as good consequences?
Who is the primary beneficiary of moral action?
How are the consequences judged and who judges them?
One way to divide various consequentialisms is by the types of consequences that are taken to matter most, that is, which consequences count as good states of affairs. According to , a good action is one that results in an increase in a positive effect, and the best action is one that results in that effect for the greatest number. Closely related is
consequentialism, according to which a full, flourishing life, which may or may not be the same as enjoying a great deal of pleasure, is the ultimate aim. Similarly, one might adopt an aesthetic consequentialism, in which the ultimate aim is to produce beauty. However, one might fix on non-psychological goods as the relevant effect. Thus, one might pursue an increase in
instead of something like the more ephemeral "pleasure". Other theories adopt a package of several goods, all to be promoted equally. Whether a particular consequentialist theory focuses on a single good or many, conflicts and tensions between different good states of affairs are to be expected and must be adjudicated.
Main article:
Utilitarianism is an ethical theory that argues the proper course of action is one that maximizes a positive effect, such as "happiness", "welfare", or the ability to live according to personal preferences.
are influential proponents of this school of thought. In A Fragment on Government Bentham says 'it is the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and wrong' and describes this as a fundamental . In An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation he talks of 'the principle of utility' but later prefers "the greatest happiness principle".
Utilitarianism is the paradigmatic example of a consequentialist moral theory. This form of utilitarianism holds that what matters is the aggregate positive effect of everyone and not only of any one person. , in his exposition of utilitarianism, proposed a hierarchy of pleasures, meaning that the pursuit of certain kinds of pleasure is more highly valued than the pursuit of other pleasures. Other noteworthy proponents of utilitarianism are neuroscientist , author of , and moral philosopher , author of, amongst other works, .
There are two types of utilitarianism,
and . In act utilitarianism the principle of utility is applied directly to each alternative act in a situation of choice. The right act is then defined as the one which brings about the best results (or the least amount of bad results). In rule utilitarianism the principle of utility is used to determine the validity of rules of conduct (moral principles). A rule like promise-keeping is established by looking at the consequences of a world in which people broke promises at will and a world in which promises were binding. Right and wrong are then defined as following or breaking those rules.
Main article:
Deontological ethics or deontology (from
δ?ον, deon, "obligation, duty"; and -λογ?α, ) is an approach to ethics that determines goodness or rightness from examining , or the rules and duties that the person doing the act strove to fulfill. This is in contrast to , in which rightness is based on the consequences of an act, and not the act by itself. In deontology, an act may be considered right even if the act produces a bad consequence, if it follows the rule that "one should do unto others as they would have done unto them", and even if the person who does the act lacks virtue and had a bad intention in doing the act.[] According to deontology, we have a duty to act in a way that does those things that are
good as acts ("truth-telling" for example), or follow an objectively obligatory rule (as in ). For deontologists, the ends or consequences of our actions are not important in and of themselves, and our intentions are not important in and of themselves.
Immanuel Kant's theory of ethics is considered deontological for several different reasons. First, Kant argues that to act in the morally right way, people must act from duty (deon). Second, Kant argued that it was not the consequences of actions that make them right or wrong but the motives (maxime) of the person who carries out the action.
Kant's argument that to act in the morally right way, one must act from duty, begins with an argument that the highest good must be both good in itself, and good without qualification. Something is 'good in itself' when it is , and 'good without qualification' when the addition of that thing never makes a situation ethically worse. Kant then argues that those things that are usually thought to be good, such as , perseverance and , fail to be either intrinsically good or good without qualification. Pleasure, for example, appears to not be good without qualification, because when people take pleasure in watching someone suffer, they make the situation ethically worse. He concludes that there is only one thing that is truly good:
Nothing in the world—indeed nothing even beyond the world—can possibly be conceived which could be called good without qualification except a good will.
Main article:
Associated with the , , , and especially , pragmatic ethics holds that moral correctness evolves similarly to scientific knowledge: socially over the course of many lifetimes. Thus, we should prioritize social reform over attempts to account for consequences, individual virtue or duty (although these may be worthwhile attempts, provided social reform is provided for).
Main article:
Role ethics is an ethical theory based on
roles. Unlike , role ethics is not individualistic. Morality is derived from a person's relationship with their community.
ethics is an example of role ethics. Confucian roles center around the concept of
or xiao, a respect for family members. According to Roger Ames and Henry Rosemont, "Confucian normativity is defined by living one's family roles to maximum effect." Morality is determined through a person's fulfillment of a role, such as that of a parent or a child. Confucian roles are not , and originate through the xin, or human emotions.
Main article:
ethics is an ethical theory based on the studies of anarchist thinkers. The biggest contributor to the anarchist ethics is the Russian zoologist, geographer, economist and political activist . The anarchist ethics is a big and vague field which can depend upon different historical situations and different anarchist thinkers, but as Peter Kropotkin explains, "any “bourgeois” or “proletarian” ethics rests, after all, on the common basis, on the common ethnological foundation, which at times exerts a very strong influence on the principles of the class or group morality." Still, most of the anarchist ethics schools are based on three fundamental ideas, which are: "solidarity, equality and justice". Kropotkin argues that Ethics is evolutionary and is inherited as a sort of a social instinct through History, and by so, he rejects any religious and transcendental explanation of ethics.
Main article:
This article or section possibly contains
of published material that conveys ideas not
to the original sources. Relevant discussion may be found on the . (July 2009)
The 20th century saw a remarkable expansion and evolution of critical theory, following on earlier
efforts to locate individuals within larger structural frameworks of ideology and action.
challenged the possibilities of individual agency and the coherence of the notion of the 'individual' itself.[] As critical theory developed in the later 20th century,
sought to problematize human relationships to knowledge and 'objective' reality.
argued that access to meaning and the 'real' was always deferred, and sought to demonstrate via recourse to the linguistic realm that "there is nothing outside context" ("il n'y a pas de hors-texte" is often mistranslated as "there is nothing outside the text"); at the same time,
theorised that signs and symbols or simulacra mask reality (and eventually the absence of reality itself), particularly in the consumer world.
Post-structuralism and
argue that ethics must study the complex and relational conditions of actions. A simple alignment of ideas of right and particular acts is not possible. There will always be an ethical remainder that cannot be taken into account or often even recognized. Such theorists find narrative (or, following Nietzsche and Foucault, ) to be a helpful tool for understanding ethics because narrative is always about particular lived experiences in all their complexity rather than the assignment of an idea or norm to separate and individuated actions.
is best described as Modernity without illusion, the illusion being the belief that humanity can be repaired by some ethic principle. Postmodernity can be seen in this light as accepting the messy nature of humanity as unchangeable.
David Couzens Hoy states that 's writings on the face of the Other and 's meditations on the relevance of death to ethics are signs of the "ethical turn" in Continental philosophy that occurred in the 1980s and 1990s. Hoy describes post-critique ethics as the "obligations that present themselves as necessarily to be fulfilled but are neither forced on one or are enforceable" (2004, p. 103).
Hoy's post-critique model uses the term ethical resistance. Examples of this would be an individual's resistance to consumerism in a retreat to a simpler but perhaps harder lifestyle, or an individual's resistance to a terminal illness. Hoy describes Levinas's account as "not the attempt to use power against itself, or to mobilize sectors of the population to exert t the ethical resistance is instead the resistance of the powerless"(2004, p. 8).
Hoy concludes that
The ethical resistance of the powerless others to our capacity to exert power over them is therefore what imposes unenforceable obligations on us. The obligations are unenforceable precisely because of the other's lack of power. That actions are at once obligatory and at the same time unenforceable is what put them in the category of the ethical. Obligations that were enforced would, by the virtue of the force behind them, not be freely undertaken and would not be in the realm of the ethical. (2004, p.184)
In present-day terms the powerless may include the unborn, the terminally sick, the aged, the insane, and non-human animals. It is in these areas that ethical action in Hoy's sense will apply. Until legislation or the state apparatus enforces a moral order that addresses the causes of resistance these issues will remain in the ethical realm. For example, should animal experimentation become illegal in a society, it will no longer be an ethical issue on Hoy's definition. Likewise one hundred and fifty years ago, not having a black slave in America would have been an ethical choice. This later issue has been absorbed into the fabric of an enforceable social order and is therefore no longer an ethical issue in Hoy's sense.
Main article:
Applied ethics is a discipline of philosophy that attempts to apply ethical theory to real-life situations. The discipline has many specialized fields, such as , , , public service ethics and .
This section needs additional citations for . Please help
by . Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (May 2009)
Applied ethics is used in some aspects of determining public policy, as well as by individuals facing difficult decisions. The sort of questions addressed by applied ethics include: "Is getting an abortion immoral?" "Is euthanasia immoral?" "Is affirmative action right or wrong?" "What are human rights, and how do we determine them?" "Do animals have rights as well?" and "Do individuals have the right of self determination?"
A more specific question could be: "If someone else can make better out of his/her life than I can, is it then moral to sacrifice myself for them if needed?" Without these questions there is no clear fulcrum on which to balance law, politics, and the practice of arbitration — in fact, no common assumptions of all participants—so the ability to formulate the questions are prior to rights balancing. But not all questions studied in applied ethics concern public policy. For example, making ethical judgments regarding questions such as, "Is lying always wrong?" and, "If not, when is it permissible?" is prior to any etiquette.
People in-general are more comfortable with dichotomies (two opposites). However, in ethics the issues are most often multifaceted and the best proposed actions address many different areas concurrently. In ethical decisions the answer is almost never a "yes or no", "right or wrong" statement. Many buttons are pushed so that the overall condition is improved and not to the benefit of any particular faction.
Main article:
Bioethics is the study of controversial ethics brought about by advances in
and . Bioethicists are concerned with the ethical questions that arise in the relationships among , , , , , and . It also includes the study of the more commonplace questions of values () that arise in primary care and other branches of medicine.
Bioethics also needs to address emerging biotechnologies that affect basic biology and future humans. These developments include , , , astroethics and life in space, and manipulation of basic biology through altered DNA, XNA and proteins,e.g.- "three parent baby,where baby is born from genetically modified embryos, would have DNA from a mother, a father and from a female donor. Correspondingly, new bioethics also need to address life at its core. For example,
value organic gene/protein life itself and seek to propagate it. With such life-centered principles, ethics may secure a cosmological future for life.
Main article:
Business ethics (also corporate ethics) is a form of
that examines ethical principles and moral or ethical problems that arise in a business environment, including fields like . It applies to all aspects of business conduct and is relevant to the conduct of individuals and entire organizations.
Business ethics has both
and descriptive dimensions. As a corporate practice and a career specialization, the field is primarily normative. Academics attempting to understand business behavior employ descriptive methods. The range and quantity of business ethical issues reflects the interaction of profit-maximizing behavior with non-economic concerns. Interest in business ethics accelerated dramatically during the 1980s and 1990s, both within major corporations and within academia. For example, today most major corporations promote their commitment to non-economic values under headings such as ethics codes and social responsibility charters. Adam Smith said, "People of the same trade seldom meet together, even for merriment and diversion, but the conversation ends in a conspiracy against the public, or in some contrivance to raise prices." Governments use laws and regulations to point business behavior in what they perceive to be beneficial directions. Ethics implicitly regulates areas and details of behavior that lie beyond governmental control. The emergence of large corporations with limited relationships and sensitivity to the communities in which they operate accelerated the development of formal ethics regimes.
Relational ethics are related to an .:62–63 They are used in qualitative research, especially ethnography and autoethnography. Researchers who employ relational ethics value and respect the connection between themselves and the people they study, and "between researchers and the communities in which they live and work" (Ellis, 2007, p. 4). Relational ethics also help researchers understand difficult issues such as conducting research on intimate others that have died and developing friendships with their participants. Relational ethics in close personal relationships form a central concept of .
Main article:
In Moral Machines: Teaching Robots Right from Wrong, Wendell Wallach and Colin Allen conclude that issues in
will likely drive advancement in understanding of human ethics by forcing us to address gaps in modern normative theory and by providing a platform for experimental investigation. The effort to actually program a machine or artificial agent to behave as though instilled with a sense of ethics requires new specificity in our normative theories, especially regarding aspects customarily considered common-sense. For example, machines, unlike humans, can support a wide selection of , and controversy has arisen over the relative ethical merits of these options. This may reopen classic debates of normative ethics framed in new (highly technical) terms.
Military ethics are concerned with questions regarding the application of force and the ethos of the soldier and are often understood as applied professional ethics.
is generally seen to set the background terms of military ethics. However individual countries and traditions have different fields of attention.
Military ethics involves multiple subareas, including the following among others:
what, if any, should be the laws of war
justification for the initiation of military force
decisions about who may be targeted in warfare
decisions on choice of weaponry, and what collateral effects such weaponry may have
standards for handling military prisoners
methods of dealing with violations of the laws of war
(also known as political morality or public ethics) is the practice of making moral judgements about political action and political agents.
is a set of principles that guide public officials in their service to their constituents, including their decision-making on behalf of their constituents. Fundamental to the concept of public sector ethics is the notion that decisions and actions are based on what best serves the public's interests, as opposed to the official's personal interests (including financial interests) or self-serving political interests.
Publication ethics is the set of principles that guide the writing and publishing process for all professional publications. In order to follow the set of principles, authors should verify that the publication does not contain
or . As a way to avoid misconduct in research these principles can also be applied to experiments which are referenced or analyzed in publications by ensuring the data is recorded, honestly and accurately.
Plagiarism is the failure to give credit to another author’s work or ideas, when it is used in the publication. It is the obligation of the editor of the journal to ensure the article does not contain any plagiarism before it is published. If a publication which has already been published is proven to contain plagiarism, then the editor of the journal can proceed to have the article retracted.
Publication bias occurs when the publication is one-sided or " against results". In best practice, an author should try to include information from all parties involved, or affected by the topic. If an author is prejudiced against certain results, than it can "lead to erroneous conclusions being drawn.”
Misconduct in research can occur when information from an experiment is falsely recorded or altered. Falsely recorded information occurs when the researcher "fakes" information or data, which was not used when conducting the actual experiment. By faking the data, the researcher can alter the results from the experiment to better fit the hypothesis they originally predicted. When conducting medical research, it is important to honor the healthcare rights of a patient by protecting their
in the publication.
Main article:
Moral psychology is a field of study that began as an issue in
and that is now properly considered part of the discipline of . Some use the term "moral psychology" relatively narrowly to refer to the study of . However, others tend to use the term more broadly to include any topics at the intersection of ethics and psychology (and ). Such topics are ones that involve the mind and are relevant to moral issues. Some of the main topics of the field are , moral development,
(especially as related to ), , , , and moral disagreement.
Main article:
Evolutionary ethics concerns approaches to ethics (morality) based on the role of evolution in shaping human psychology and behavior. Such approaches may be based in scientific fields such as
or , with a focus on understanding and explaining observed ethical preferences and choices.
Main article:
Descriptive ethics is on the less philosophical end of the spectrum, since it seeks to gather particular information about how people live and draw general conclusions based on observed patterns. Abstract and theoretical questions that are more clearly philosophical—such as, "Is ethical knowledge possible?"—are not central to descriptive ethics. Descriptive ethics offers a
approach to ethics, which defines it as a social science rather than . Its examination of ethics doesn't start with a preconceived theory, but rather investigates
made by moral agents in practice. Some philosophers rely on descriptive ethics and choices made and unchallenged by a
to derive categories, which typically vary by context. This can lead to
and . These philosophers often view , , and
as more fundamental, percolating "bottom up" to imply the existence of, rather than explicitly prescribe, theories of value or of conduct. The study of descriptive ethics may include examinations of the following:
applied by various groups. Some consider aesthetics itself the basis of ethics– and a personal
developed through art and storytelling as very influential in one's later ethical choices.
Informal theories of etiquette that tend to be less rigorous and more situational. Some consider etiquette a simple negative ethics, i.e., where can one evade an uncomfortable truth without doing wrong? One notable advocate of this view is
("Miss Manners"). According to this view, ethics is more a summary of
social decisions.
Practices in arbitration and , e.g., the claim that ethics itself is a matter of balancing "right versus right," i.e., putting priorities on two things that are both right, but that must be traded off carefully in each situation.
made by ordinary people, without expert aid or advice, who , buy, and decide what is worth valuing. This is a major concern of sociology, , and .
(alphabetical list of ethics-related articles)
(list of ethics-related articles, arranged by sub-topic)
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Kidder. How Good People Make Tough Choices Rev Ed: Resolving the Dilemmas of Ethical Living.
Paul, R Elder, Linda (2006). The Miniature Guide to Understanding the Foundations of Ethical Reasoning. United States: Foundation for Critical Thinking Free Press. p. np.  .
John Deigh in Robert Audi (ed), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 1995.
. Merriam Webster 2015.
David Tanguay (January 24, 2014). . Soul of Wit. Archived from
on July 22, .
. . Archived from
on October 28, .
Miller, C. (2009). The Conditions of Moral Realism. The Journal of Philosophical Research, 34, 123-155.
Cavalier, Robert. . Online Guide to Ethics and Moral Philosophy. Archived from
on November 12, .
William S. S Mabel Lewis Sahakian (1966). Ideas of the Great Philosophers. Barnes & Noble.  .
Professor Michiel S. S. De De V Professor Pan Suk Kim (October 28, 2011). Value and Virtue in Public Administration: A Comparative Perspective. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 42.  .
Nussbaum, Martha (1987). Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach.
John Newton, Ph.D., Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century (2000). .
Ivanhoe, P.J.; Van Norden, Bryan William (2005). Readings in classical Chinese philosophy. . p. 60.  . "he advocated a form of state consequentialism, which sought to maximize three basic goods: the wealth, order, and population of the state
Fraser, Chris, "",
, Edward N. Zalta.
Loewe, M Shaughnessy, Edward L. (1999). . . p. 761.  .
Van Norden, Bryan W. (2011). Introduction to Classical Chinese Philosophy. . p. 52.  .
Jay L. G William Edelglass (June 9, 2011). . Oxford University Press. p. 62.  . The goods that serve as criteria of morality are collective or public, in contrast, for instance, to individual happiness or well-being
(1958) 33 (124): 1–19. :.
(1990) [1977]. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin.  .
(2007). The Ethics Toolkit: A Compendium of Ethical Concepts and Methods. Malden: Blackwell. pp. 57–58.  .
Bentham, Jeremy (2001). The Works of Jeremy Bentham: Published under the Superintendence of His Executor, John Bowring. Volume 1. Adamant Media Corporation. p. 18.  .
(1998). . Oxford: .  .
Olson, Robert G. 1967. 'Deontological Ethics'. In Paul Edwards (ed.) The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: : 343.
Orend, Brian. 2000. War and International Justice: A Kantian Perspective. West Waterloo, Ontario: : 19.
Kelly, Eugene. 2006. The Basics of Western Philosophy. : 160.
Kant, Immanuel. 1780. 'Preface'. In The Metaphysical Elements of Ethics. Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott
Kant, Immanuel. 1785. 'First Section: Transition from the Common Rational Knowledge of Morals to the Philosophical', .
Lafollette, Hugh, ed. (February 2000). . Blackwell Philosophy Guides (1 ed.). .  .
Roger T. Ames (April 30, 2011). Confucian Role Ethics: A Vocabulary. University of Hawai?i Press.  .
Chris F Dan R Timothy O'Leary (May 1, 2011). . Hong Kong University Press. pp. 17–35.  .
Wonsuk C Leah Kalmanson (November 8, 2010). . . p. 68.  .
. Archived from
on October 23, .
Freemont, P. F.; Kitney, R. I. (2012). Synthetic Biology. New Jersey: .  .
Mautner, Michael N. (2009).
23: 433–440. :.  .
Mautner, Michael N. (2000).
(). Washington D. C.:
().  .
Smith, A () An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, p. 55
Berle, A. A., & Means, G. C. (1932). The Modern Corporation and Private Property. New Jersey: Transaction Publishers. In this book, Berle and Means observe, "Corporations have ceased to be merely legal devices through which the private business transactions of individuals may be carried on. Though still much used for this purpose, the corporate form has acquired a much larger significance. The corporation has, in fact, become both a method of property tenure and a means of organizing economic life. Grown to tremendous proportions, there may be said to have evolved a 'corporate system'—as there once was a feudal system—which has attracted to itself a combination of attributes and powers, and has attained a degree of prominence entitling it to be dealt with as a major social institution. ... We are examining this institution probably before it has attained its zenith. Spectacular as its rise has been, every indication seems to be that the system will move forward to proportions which stagger imagination today ... They [management] have placed the community in a position to demand that the modern corporation serve not only the owners ... but all society." p. 1.
, p. 17
Carol GILLIGAN (June 30, 2009). IN A DIFFERENT VOICE. Harvard University Press.  .
Ellis, C. (2007). Telling secrets, revealing lives: Relational ethics in research with intimate others. Qualitative Inquiry, 13, 3-29.
Ellis, C. (1986). Fisher folk. Two communities on Chesapeake Bay. Lexington: .
Ellis, C. (1995).Final negotiations: A story of love, loss, and chronic illness. Philadelphia: .
Wallach, W Allen, Colin (November 2008). Moral Machines: Teaching Robots Right from Wrong. USA: .  .
Cook, Martin L.; Syse, Henrik (2010). "What Should We Mean by 'Military Ethics'?". Journal of Military Ethics 9 (2). p. 122.
(in French). France: L'Harmattan.  .
Thompson, Dennis F. "Political Ethics." International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette (Blackwell Publishing, 2012).
See, for example, work of Institute for Local Government, at .
Morton, Neil (October 2009). . Pediatric Anesthesia 19 (10): .
Wager, E; Fiack, S; Graf, C; Robinson, A; Rowlands, I (31 March 2009). . Journal of Medical Ethics 35: 348–353.
Scollon, Ron (June 1999). . Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 9: 188–190.
Wager, E Williams, Peter (September 2011). . Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (9): 567–570.
Sanjeev, Handa (2008). . Indian Journal of Dermatology Venereology and Leprology 74 (4): 301–303.
Sigelman, Lee (2000). . Political Analysis 8 (2): 201–210.
Peters, Jamie L.; Sutton, Alex J.; Jones, David R.; Abrams, Keith R.; Rushton, L Moreno, Santiago G. (July 2010). "Assessing publication bias in meta-analysis in the presence of between-study heterogeneity". Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series A (Statistics in Society) 173 (3): 575–591.
Smith, Richard (July 26, 1997). . British Medical Journal 315 (7102): 201–202.
See, for example, Lapsley (2006) and "moral psychology" (2007).
See, for example, Doris & Stich (2008) and Wallace (2007). Wallace writes: "Moral psychology is the study of morality in its psychological dimensions" (p. 86).
See Doris & Stich (2008), §1.
Doris Schroeder. . Archived from
on October 7, .
Hoy, D. (2005), Critical resistance from poststructuralism to postcritique, , Massachusetts.
Lyon, D. (1999), Postmodernity, 2nd ed, , Buckingham.
Singer, P. (2000), Writings on an ethical life, , London.
offers many suggestions on what to read, depending on the student's familiarity with the subject:
. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, editors. Second edition in three volumes. New York: Routledge, 2002. A scholarly encyclopedia with over 500 signed,
articles, mostly on topics and figures of, or of special interest in, .
1998: "The violence and the search for new values" in Euskal Herria krisian, (Elkar, 1999), pp. 11–116.
De Finance, Joseph, An Ethical Inquiry, Rome, Editrice Pontificia Università Gregoriana, 1991.
, "Doing Christian Ethics from the Margins," Orbis Books, 2004.
1995, The Gift of Death, translated by David Wills, , Chicago.
Fagothey, Austin, Right and Reason, Tan Books & Publishers, Rockford, Illinois, 2000.
1969, Totality and infinity, an essay on exteriority, translated by Alphonso Lingis, , Pittsburgh.
(March 11, 2004).
2007., . Skepticism in Ethics (1989).
, Morality and the Good Life: An Introduction to Ethics Through Classical Sources, New York: , 1984.
Vendemiati, Aldo, In the First Person, An Outline of General Ethics, Rome, Urbaniana University Press, 2004.
John Paul II, Encyclical Letter , August 6, 1993.
D'Urance, Michel, Jalons pour une éthique rebelle, Aléthéia, Paris, 2005.
John Newton, Ph.D. Complete Conduct Principles for the 21st Century, 2000. .
Guy Cools & Pascal Gielen, The Ethics of Art. Valiz: Amsterdam, 2014.
Lafollette, Hugh [ed.]: Ethics in Practice: An Anthology. Wiley Blackwell, 4th edition, Oxford 2014.
Wikimedia Commons has media related to .
in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.
Wikiversity has learning materials about
Wikisource has original works on the topic:
entry in the
by Paul Newall, aimed at beginners.
, 2d ed., 1973. by
podcast series podcast exploring ethical dilemmas in everyday life.
World's largest library for ethical issues in medicine and biomedical research
entry in Encyclopaedia Britannica by
on Philosophy Archive
Resources, events, and research on a range of ethical subjects from a Christian perspective.
Resources for analyzing real-world ethical issues and tools to address them.
: Hidden categories:

我要回帖

更多关于 public morality 的文章

 

随机推荐